Difference between revisions of "User:Michiexile/MATH198/Lecture 1"

From HaskellWiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Line 49: Line 49:
 
;Epimorphism:A morphism that is right-cancellable. Corresponds to surjective functions. We say that ''f'' is an epimorphism if for any <math>g_1,g_2</math>, the equation <math>g_1f = g_2f</math> implies <math>g_1=g_2</math>.
 
;Epimorphism:A morphism that is right-cancellable. Corresponds to surjective functions. We say that ''f'' is an epimorphism if for any <math>g_1,g_2</math>, the equation <math>g_1f = g_2f</math> implies <math>g_1=g_2</math>.
 
Note, by the way, that cancellability does not imply the existence of an inverse. Epi's and mono's that have inverses realizing their cancellability are called ''split''.
 
Note, by the way, that cancellability does not imply the existence of an inverse. Epi's and mono's that have inverses realizing their cancellability are called ''split''.
;Isomorphism;A morphism is an isomorphism if it has an inverse.
+
;Isomorphism:A morphism is an isomorphism if it has an inverse. Split epi and split mono imply isomorphism.
  +
;Automorphism:An automorphism is an endomorphism that is an isomorphism.
   
 
==Objects==
 
==Objects==

Revision as of 13:38, 27 August 2009

Welcome, administrativia

Introduction

Why this course? What will we cover? What do we require?

Category

A graph is a collection of vertices and a collection of arrows. The structure of the graph is captured in the existence of two functions, that we shall call source and target, both going from to . In other words, each arrow has a source and a target.

We denote by [v,w] the collection of arrows with source v and target w.

A category is a graph with some special structure:

  • Each [v,w] is a set and equipped with a composition operation . In other words, any two arrows, such that the target of one is the source of the other, can be composed to give a new arrow with target and source from the ones left out.

We write if .

=>

  • The composition of arrows is associative.
  • Each vertex v has a dedicated arrow with source and target v, called the identity arrow.
  • Each identity arrow is a left- and right-identity for the composition operation.

The composition of with is denoted by . A mnemonic here is that you write things so associativity looks right. Hence, (gf)(x) = g(f(x)). This will make more sense once we get around to generalized elements later on.

Examples

  • The empty category with no vertices and no arrows.
  • The category 1 with a single vertex and only its identity arrow.
  • The category 2 with two objects, their identity arrows and the arrow .
  • For vertices take vector spaces. For arrows, take linear maps. This is a category, the identity arrow is just the identity map and composition is just function composition.
  • For vertices take finite sets. For arrows, take functions.
  • For vertices take logical propositions. For arrows take proofs in propositional logic. The identity arrow is the empty proof: P proves P without an actual proof. And if you can prove P using Q and then R using P, then this composes to a proof of R using Q.
  • For vertices, take data types. For arrows take (computable) functions. This forms a category, in which we can discuss an abstraction that mirrors most of Haskell. There are issues making Haskell not quite a category on its own, but we get close enough to draw helpful conclusions and analogies.
  • Suppose P is a set equipped with a partial ordering relation <. Then we can form a category out of this set with elements for vertices and with a single element in [v,w] if and only if v<w. Then the transitivity and reflexivity of partial orderings show that this forms a category.

Some language we want settled:

A category is concrete if it is like the vector spaces and the sets among the examples - the collection of all sets-with-specific-additional-structure equipped with all functions-respecting-that-structure. We require already that [v,w] is always a set.

A category is small if the collection of all vertices, too, is a set.

Morphisms

The arrows of a category are called morphisms. This is derived from homomorphisms.

Some arrows have special properties that make them extra helpful; and we'll name them:

Endomorphism
A morphism with the same object as source and target.
Monomorphism
A morphism that is left-cancellable. Corresponds to injective functions. We say that f is a monomorphism if for any , the equation implies . In other words, with a concrete perspective, f doesn't introduce additional relations when applied.
Epimorphism
A morphism that is right-cancellable. Corresponds to surjective functions. We say that f is an epimorphism if for any , the equation implies .

Note, by the way, that cancellability does not imply the existence of an inverse. Epi's and mono's that have inverses realizing their cancellability are called split.

Isomorphism
A morphism is an isomorphism if it has an inverse. Split epi and split mono imply isomorphism.
Automorphism
An automorphism is an endomorphism that is an isomorphism.

Objects

In a category, we use a different name for the vertices: objects. This comes from the roots in describing concrete categories - thus while objects may be actual mathematical objects, but they may just as well be completely different.

Some objects, if they exist, give us strong